Law in Contemporary Society

View   r5  >  r4  >  r3  >  r2  >  r1
CamilaTapernouxFirstPaper 5 - 22 Jan 2013 - Main.IanSullivan
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaperSpring2012"
 

Property Rights and Transcendental Nonsense


CamilaTapernouxFirstPaper 4 - 23 Apr 2012 - Main.CamilaTapernoux
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
Line: 11 to 11
 Rousseau famously said that “the first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself of saying this is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him, was the real founder of civil society. From how many crimes, wars, and murders, from how many horrors and misfortunes might not any one have saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or filling up the ditch, and crying to his fellows: Beware of listening to this imposter; you are undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to us all, and the earth itself to nobody.”
Changed:
<
<
I have been trying to wrap my mind around the Eben’s and his academic peer’s approach to property rights. I came to law school because I was interested in IP law, so naturally I have been intrigued by the arguments against IP in our readings and in Eben’s scholarship.
>
>
The argument against property rights has been around for, well, as long as there have been property rights. And so it goes today with the arguments against intellectual property rights. I have been trying to wrap my mind around Eben’s and his academic peer’s approach to this debate, because the main reason I came to law school because out of an interest in IP law, and a desire to shape the direction of this evolving field. A vague underlying goal was the desire to adjust, or change, the system so that pharmaceutical development remained incentivized while distribution became equalized, namely with regards to providing needed drugs that are still under patent to those in third world countries who cannot afford them.
 

A (Very Small) Sampling of the Arguments

Changed:
<
<
The first criticism I came to was that of Felix Cohen in his consideration of What’s In a Trade Name? He provides the rhetoric of courts in enforcing unfair competition laws (through trademark protection) as an example of circular reasoning, of transcendental nonsense. Trademark law, he says, “purports to base legal protection upon economic value, when, as a matter of actual fact, the economic value of a sales device depends upon the extent to which it will be legally protected.” He boils the problem down to the existence of property rights at all, and contends that the actual effect of unfair competition is to “create and distribute a new source of economic wealth or power…through establishing inequality in the commercial exploitation of language.” Professor Moglen’s dotCommunist Manifesto extends Cohen’s wealth redistribution argument beyond trademark law to Intellectual Property law as a whole. He says that the existence of Intellectual Property “is solely due to its non-existence in the hands of everyone else,” that “the necessary condition for [its] existence is the non-existence of any such property for the immense majority of society.”

Wasn't it Marx who said that, rather than me?

Moglen then addresses the same counterargument that N. Stephen Kinsella explains in Against Intellectual Property, which is that “wealth is optimized, or at least increased, by granting copyright and patent monopolies that encourage authors and inventors to innovate and create.” Moglen points out that according this argument, “there ought to have been no music, art, technology, or learning before the advent of the bourgeoisie, which alone conceived of subjecting the entirety of knowledge and culture to the cash nexus.

>
>
I began looking for answers by surveying some of the arguments advocating to various degrees the abolishment of IP. The first criticism of the system I came to was that of Felix Cohen in his consideration of What’s In a Trade Name? He provides the rhetoric of courts in enforcing unfair competition laws (through trademark protection) as an example of circular reasoning, of transcendental nonsense. Trademark law, he says, “purports to base legal protection upon economic value, when, as a matter of actual fact, the economic value of a sales device depends upon the extent to which it will be legally protected.” He boils the problem down to the existence of property rights at all, and contends that the actual effect of unfair competition is to “create and distribute a new source of economic wealth or power…through establishing inequality in the commercial exploitation of language.” Professor Moglen’s dotCommunist Manifesto extends Cohen’s wealth redistribution argument beyond trademark law to Intellectual Property law as a whole. He applies Marx’s argument to Intellectual Property, that IP’s existence “is solely due to its non-existence in the hands of everyone else,” that “the necessary condition for [its] existence is the non-existence of any such property for the immense majority of society.”
 
Changed:
<
<
Are you sure that wasn't Marx?

Faced with the advent of free production and free technology, with free software, and with the resulting development of free distribution technology, this argument simply denies the visible and unanswerable facts. Fact is subordinated to dogma, in which the arrangements that briefly characterized intellectual production and cultural distribution during the short heyday of the bourgeoisie are said, despite the evidence of both past and present, to be the only structures possible.”

That was I.
>
>
Moglen then addresses the same counterargument that N. Stephen Kinsella explains in Against Intellectual Property, which is that “wealth is optimized, or at least increased, by granting copyright and patent monopolies that encourage authors and inventors to innovate and create. He uses Marx’s argument to aptly attack this view by pointing out that “there ought to have been no music, art, technology, or learning before the advent of the bourgeoisie, which alone conceived of subjecting the entirety of knowledge and culture to the cash nexus.” According to Moglen, then, when “faced with the advent of free production and free technology, with free software, and with the resulting development of free distribution technology, this argument simply denies the visible and unanswerable facts. Fact is subordinated to dogma, in which the arrangements that briefly characterized intellectual production and cultural distribution during the short heyday of the bourgeoisie are said, despite the evidence of both past and present, to be the only structures possible.”
 Complementing this practical take on the illegitimacy of the utilitarian argument, Kinsella provides a more theoretical criticism: “Wealth maximization is not the goal of law; rather, the goal is justice—giving each man his due. Even if overall wealth is increased due to IP laws, it does not follow that this allegedly desirable result justifies the unethical violation of some individuals’ rights to use their own property as they see fit.” Reading this immediately brought to mind our discussion of the law treating the rich man kindly and the poor man justly. Among the myriad of arguments against IP that I have come across the past few days, some coherent, some too dense for me to understand, and some too unsubstantiated to hold my attention, perhaps this is the one from which all the others stem.

Deleted:
<
<

A World Without Private Property

Yet as convincing as the impassioned critiques of IP law, or of property law in general, may be, they are functionally useless without an accompanying solution. And I wonder if grouping three distinct forms of property rights under the uniform umbrella of “intellectual property law” does more harm to the movement for their abolition than good. Through reading criticisms of these systems I’ve begun to feel that they are more different than they are similar, and that a comprehensive plan to overhaul or abolish all three systems would be like using the same strategy to stage revolutions in North Korea, China, and Thailand. I similarly question if desiring a revolution of the IP system necessitates advocating a revolution of property law entirely. Does being against socialism or monarchy require opposition to any and all forms of government?

 
Changed:
<
<
Perhaps this question stems from the fact that I find it easier to accept rhetoric against intellectual property rights because they rely more on transcendental nonsense than defenses of private property rights for real property. As a result, the IP system can lead to results entirely in conflict with the traditional property system. For example, one of the first things we learned in Property last semester was the a property right meant the right to do whatever you want with your property so long as it did not harm others. Yet, as Kinsella explains, intellectual property rights can allow the holder to do exactly that. If I hold a patent on a procedure to test for genetic predisposition for a type of cancer, I can prevent you from using your own labor and materials to build the machine and carry out the test, even if you independently learned how to build the machine and perform the test yourself. And there we have yet another instance of the rich man being treated kindly, benefitting from advances in technology and receiving preventive treatment, while the poor man is treated justly, if justice in such a situation is allowing nature to take its course. But all this tells me is what is wrong. I am much more interested in how to fix it.
>
>

Free Software vs Free Pharma

 
Changed:
<
<
You can make this better by keeping three considerations firmly in mind:
>
>
Yet as convincing as the impassioned critiques of IP law, or of property law in general, may be, they are functionally useless without an accompanying solution. And I wonder if grouping three distinct forms of property rights under the uniform umbrella of “intellectual property law” does more harm to the movement for their abolition than good. As Eben pointed out, “[t]he phrase "intellectual property" not only wraps up incommensurable legal arrangements such as copyright and patent together, by doing so it creates a metaphorical relationship to real property that is deceptive.” So is there anything to be learned from the “Free Software” movement that could be applied to some sort of “Free Pharma” movement in the future? I’m not sure. In “Freeing the Mind,” Eben contemplates that “[i]f I can provide to everyone all goods of intellectual value or beauty, for the same price that I can provide the first copy of those works to anyone, why is it ever moral to exclude anyone from anything? If you could feed everyone on earth at the cost of baking one loaf and pressing a button, what would be the moral case for charging more for bread than some people could afford to pay?” And this argument applies seamlessly to the zero-marginal-cost good of software, but loses traction in the world of pharmaceutical development.
 
Changed:
<
<
  1. The phrase "intellectual property" not only wraps up incommensurable legal arrangements such as copyright and patent together, by doing so it creates a metaphorical relationship to real property that is deceptive;
  2. Bitstreams, which have zero marginal cost, are distinctively unlike the goods traditionally considered by economics, which have non-zero marginal cost. The theory of the firm correctly predicts that at equilibrium in a competitive market, price equals marginal cost. "Intellectual property" in digital information is a way of preventing a free market; and
  3. The alternative you are looking for already exists in the commons-based sharing economies: free software and creative commons.
>
>
There is, however, conceivably a parallel in the fact that once a drug is developed, the cost of mass producing the pills or serums or what have you is but a miniscule percentage of the cost of development. Another possible similarity is in the incremental nature of innovation in both software and pharma. Eben describes executable software as “an inherently incremental intellectual product,” which, he points out, is a technical argument against the application of the patent system to it. His reasoning is that the “appropriate invocation of the principal of novelty and non-obviousness to software results in zero software patents. All persons reasonably skilled in the art are capable of achieving each result incrementally, from where the art is at any given moment. But more importantly, for our purposes, the process of making software is massively parallelizable, when the costs of communication and coordination are reduced near zero.” It may be that the capacity of pharma R&D has reached a similar point of incremental progress. If that were the case, then Eben’s perspective of the evolution of governmental spectrum regulation might also apply to governmental pharma regulation, namely, that the problem has gone away, but the underlying system of social relations has not changed.
 
Changed:
<
<
You would have had an easier time of it in this draft if you had read more of my writing than just the dotCommunist Manifesto. You might try Freeing the Mind, for a start.
>
>
Perhaps by carrying out a more in depth analysis of these similarities, it will be possible to present a unique proposition of a way to change the patent system as it relates to pharmaceutical development in order to eliminate the barriers that that system creates to the distribution of the output whose production it seeks to incentivize—drugs—everywhere it is needed.
 

CamilaTapernouxFirstPaper 3 - 23 Apr 2012 - Main.CamilaTapernoux
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"

CamilaTapernouxFirstPaper 2 - 22 Apr 2012 - Main.EbenMoglen
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
Deleted:
<
<
 

Property Rights and Transcendental Nonsense

Line: 20 to 19
 The first criticism I came to was that of Felix Cohen in his consideration of What’s In a Trade Name? He provides the rhetoric of courts in enforcing unfair competition laws (through trademark protection) as an example of circular reasoning, of transcendental nonsense. Trademark law, he says, “purports to base legal protection upon economic value, when, as a matter of actual fact, the economic value of a sales device depends upon the extent to which it will be legally protected.” He boils the problem down to the existence of property rights at all, and contends that the actual effect of unfair competition is to “create and distribute a new source of economic wealth or power…through establishing inequality in the commercial exploitation of language.” Professor Moglen’s dotCommunist Manifesto extends Cohen’s wealth redistribution argument beyond trademark law to Intellectual Property law as a whole. He says that the existence of Intellectual Property “is solely due to its non-existence in the hands of everyone else,” that “the necessary condition for [its] existence is the non-existence of any such property for the immense majority of society.”
Changed:
<
<
Moglen then addresses the same counterargument that N. Stephen Kinsella explains in Against Intellectual Property, which is that “wealth is optimized, or at least increased, by granting copyright and patent monopolies that encourage authors and inventors to innovate and create.” Moglen points out that according this argument, “there ought to have been no music, art, technology, or learning before the advent of the bourgeoisie, which alone conceived of subjecting the entirety of knowledge and culture to the cash nexus. Faced with the advent of free production and free technology, with free software, and with the resulting development of free distribution technology, this argument simply denies the visible and unanswerable facts. Fact is subordinated to dogma, in which the arrangements that briefly characterized intellectual production and cultural distribution during the short heyday of the bourgeoisie are said, despite the evidence of both past and present, to be the only structures possible.”
>
>
Wasn't it Marx who said that, rather than me?

Moglen then addresses the same counterargument that N. Stephen Kinsella explains in Against Intellectual Property, which is that “wealth is optimized, or at least increased, by granting copyright and patent monopolies that encourage authors and inventors to innovate and create.” Moglen points out that according this argument, “there ought to have been no music, art, technology, or learning before the advent of the bourgeoisie, which alone conceived of subjecting the entirety of knowledge and culture to the cash nexus.

Are you sure that wasn't Marx?

Faced with the advent of free production and free technology, with free software, and with the resulting development of free distribution technology, this argument simply denies the visible and unanswerable facts. Fact is subordinated to dogma, in which the arrangements that briefly characterized intellectual production and cultural distribution during the short heyday of the bourgeoisie are said, despite the evidence of both past and present, to be the only structures possible.”

That was I.
 Complementing this practical take on the illegitimacy of the utilitarian argument, Kinsella provides a more theoretical criticism: “Wealth maximization is not the goal of law; rather, the goal is justice—giving each man his due. Even if overall wealth is increased due to IP laws, it does not follow that this allegedly desirable result justifies the unethical violation of some individuals’ rights to use their own property as they see fit.” Reading this immediately brought to mind our discussion of the law treating the rich man kindly and the poor man justly. Among the myriad of arguments against IP that I have come across the past few days, some coherent, some too dense for me to understand, and some too unsubstantiated to hold my attention, perhaps this is the one from which all the others stem.
Line: 32 to 41
 Perhaps this question stems from the fact that I find it easier to accept rhetoric against intellectual property rights because they rely more on transcendental nonsense than defenses of private property rights for real property. As a result, the IP system can lead to results entirely in conflict with the traditional property system. For example, one of the first things we learned in Property last semester was the a property right meant the right to do whatever you want with your property so long as it did not harm others. Yet, as Kinsella explains, intellectual property rights can allow the holder to do exactly that. If I hold a patent on a procedure to test for genetic predisposition for a type of cancer, I can prevent you from using your own labor and materials to build the machine and carry out the test, even if you independently learned how to build the machine and perform the test yourself. And there we have yet another instance of the rich man being treated kindly, benefitting from advances in technology and receiving preventive treatment, while the poor man is treated justly, if justice in such a situation is allowing nature to take its course. But all this tells me is what is wrong. I am much more interested in how to fix it.
Added:
>
>
You can make this better by keeping three considerations firmly in mind:
 
Changed:
<
<

You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable. To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" character on the next two lines:
>
>
  1. The phrase "intellectual property" not only wraps up incommensurable legal arrangements such as copyright and patent together, by doing so it creates a metaphorical relationship to real property that is deceptive;
  2. Bitstreams, which have zero marginal cost, are distinctively unlike the goods traditionally considered by economics, which have non-zero marginal cost. The theory of the firm correctly predicts that at equilibrium in a competitive market, price equals marginal cost. "Intellectual property" in digital information is a way of preventing a free market; and
  3. The alternative you are looking for already exists in the commons-based sharing economies: free software and creative commons.
 
Changed:
<
<
>
>
You would have had an easier time of it in this draft if you had read more of my writing than just the dotCommunist Manifesto. You might try Freeing the Mind, for a start.
 
Deleted:
<
<
Note: TWiki has strict formatting rules for preference declarations. Make sure you preserve the three spaces, asterisk, and extra space at the beginning of these lines. If you wish to give access to any other users simply add them to the comma separated ALLOWTOPICVIEW list.
 \ No newline at end of file
Added:
>
>
 \ No newline at end of file

CamilaTapernouxFirstPaper 1 - 16 Feb 2012 - Main.CamilaTapernoux
Line: 1 to 1
Added:
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"

Property Rights and Transcendental Nonsense

-- By CamilaTapernoux - 16 Feb 2012

Introduction

Rousseau famously said that “the first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself of saying this is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him, was the real founder of civil society. From how many crimes, wars, and murders, from how many horrors and misfortunes might not any one have saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or filling up the ditch, and crying to his fellows: Beware of listening to this imposter; you are undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to us all, and the earth itself to nobody.”

I have been trying to wrap my mind around the Eben’s and his academic peer’s approach to property rights. I came to law school because I was interested in IP law, so naturally I have been intrigued by the arguments against IP in our readings and in Eben’s scholarship.

A (Very Small) Sampling of the Arguments

The first criticism I came to was that of Felix Cohen in his consideration of What’s In a Trade Name? He provides the rhetoric of courts in enforcing unfair competition laws (through trademark protection) as an example of circular reasoning, of transcendental nonsense. Trademark law, he says, “purports to base legal protection upon economic value, when, as a matter of actual fact, the economic value of a sales device depends upon the extent to which it will be legally protected.” He boils the problem down to the existence of property rights at all, and contends that the actual effect of unfair competition is to “create and distribute a new source of economic wealth or power…through establishing inequality in the commercial exploitation of language.” Professor Moglen’s dotCommunist Manifesto extends Cohen’s wealth redistribution argument beyond trademark law to Intellectual Property law as a whole. He says that the existence of Intellectual Property “is solely due to its non-existence in the hands of everyone else,” that “the necessary condition for [its] existence is the non-existence of any such property for the immense majority of society.”

Moglen then addresses the same counterargument that N. Stephen Kinsella explains in Against Intellectual Property, which is that “wealth is optimized, or at least increased, by granting copyright and patent monopolies that encourage authors and inventors to innovate and create.” Moglen points out that according this argument, “there ought to have been no music, art, technology, or learning before the advent of the bourgeoisie, which alone conceived of subjecting the entirety of knowledge and culture to the cash nexus. Faced with the advent of free production and free technology, with free software, and with the resulting development of free distribution technology, this argument simply denies the visible and unanswerable facts. Fact is subordinated to dogma, in which the arrangements that briefly characterized intellectual production and cultural distribution during the short heyday of the bourgeoisie are said, despite the evidence of both past and present, to be the only structures possible.”

Complementing this practical take on the illegitimacy of the utilitarian argument, Kinsella provides a more theoretical criticism: “Wealth maximization is not the goal of law; rather, the goal is justice—giving each man his due. Even if overall wealth is increased due to IP laws, it does not follow that this allegedly desirable result justifies the unethical violation of some individuals’ rights to use their own property as they see fit.” Reading this immediately brought to mind our discussion of the law treating the rich man kindly and the poor man justly. Among the myriad of arguments against IP that I have come across the past few days, some coherent, some too dense for me to understand, and some too unsubstantiated to hold my attention, perhaps this is the one from which all the others stem.

A World Without Private Property

Yet as convincing as the impassioned critiques of IP law, or of property law in general, may be, they are functionally useless without an accompanying solution. And I wonder if grouping three distinct forms of property rights under the uniform umbrella of “intellectual property law” does more harm to the movement for their abolition than good. Through reading criticisms of these systems I’ve begun to feel that they are more different than they are similar, and that a comprehensive plan to overhaul or abolish all three systems would be like using the same strategy to stage revolutions in North Korea, China, and Thailand. I similarly question if desiring a revolution of the IP system necessitates advocating a revolution of property law entirely. Does being against socialism or monarchy require opposition to any and all forms of government?

Perhaps this question stems from the fact that I find it easier to accept rhetoric against intellectual property rights because they rely more on transcendental nonsense than defenses of private property rights for real property. As a result, the IP system can lead to results entirely in conflict with the traditional property system. For example, one of the first things we learned in Property last semester was the a property right meant the right to do whatever you want with your property so long as it did not harm others. Yet, as Kinsella explains, intellectual property rights can allow the holder to do exactly that. If I hold a patent on a procedure to test for genetic predisposition for a type of cancer, I can prevent you from using your own labor and materials to build the machine and carry out the test, even if you independently learned how to build the machine and perform the test yourself. And there we have yet another instance of the rich man being treated kindly, benefitting from advances in technology and receiving preventive treatment, while the poor man is treated justly, if justice in such a situation is allowing nature to take its course. But all this tells me is what is wrong. I am much more interested in how to fix it.


You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable. To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" character on the next two lines:

Note: TWiki has strict formatting rules for preference declarations. Make sure you preserve the three spaces, asterisk, and extra space at the beginning of these lines. If you wish to give access to any other users simply add them to the comma separated ALLOWTOPICVIEW list.


Revision 5r5 - 22 Jan 2013 - 20:10:17 - IanSullivan
Revision 4r4 - 23 Apr 2012 - 22:26:55 - CamilaTapernoux
Revision 3r3 - 23 Apr 2012 - 18:08:49 - CamilaTapernoux
Revision 2r2 - 22 Apr 2012 - 18:33:00 - EbenMoglen
Revision 1r1 - 16 Feb 2012 - 19:36:10 - CamilaTapernoux
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM