Law in Contemporary Society

View   r18  >  r17  >  r16  >  r15  >  r14  >  r13  ...
DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 18 - 13 Jan 2012 - Main.IanSullivan
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper2010"
  There's room to expand, subtract, etc. as you think appropriate. Basically, I tried to spell out all the assumptions and reasons I thought were floating around in the background to make the message (or what I thought the message was) as clear as possible.

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 17 - 03 Jun 2010 - Main.ShawnFetty
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"
Changed:
<
<

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

The Challenge of Coordination

To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. (1)If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringerstringent? limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. (2)What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, if other countries do not cooperate, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. Sentences 1 and 2 do not seem significantly different to me. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem." I don't understand how this reference furthers your argument.

Fair point! Feel free to omit sentence 2 or 1 as you like.

"super wicked problem" is a term of art referring to problems that are very difficult solve. It's just an expression, basically.

Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needfulneeded/necessary? I understand needful is a word, but it seems odd to me. changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to support the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of internationally coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.

Arnold's Theory of Organizational Psychology

Arnold argues that creeds are “elements common to all social organizations, large and small, whatever their purpose.” 24. The reason for the ubiquity of creeds is that humans require them in order to sustain complex patterns of interaction over time. "Creeds are ubiquitous because..." As he writes, “Society functions like an anthill. If we were compelled to plan each day how to get food into New York City and waste out of it, we would be lost and people would starve.” 26.

Most of his discussion of creeds seems to have the character of an iconoclast loose in the temple. He compares "the Yale Law School" to a Laramie social club, and American political discourse to medieval theological debates about humors.

But Arnold also backs away from his "ant-hill" analogy at various points in the text. He invokes his identity as a lawyer, as opposed to social scientist, and claims he wishes to avoid "the vice of definition." Arnold seems more preoccupied with the ways in which the American creed of capitalism forecloses understanding of how American society actually works and less with the details of how creeds operate.

You're deploying Arnold as a way to think about creeds in a movement. I don't think it's necessary to spend so much time characterizing his argumentation in a paper of this length. Why not just pull out what you think is useful and move on?

Part of my project here is to help correct what I think is an incorrect interpretation of Arnold. Arnold is often characterized as as someone with an overly deterministic view of how institutions think. I'm trying to complicate that view and to defend my more (I think) subtle take on his argument. But, if you think it's a distraction from the central argument, feel to excise.

However, at one point, he discusses creeds in a light indicating a certain recognition of human capability for self-reflexivity and agency. He writes of Riverside Church's famous former pastor:

With the recognition of the fact that church creeds are not searches for universal truth, we can understand better the function of churches in society. Preachers like Harry Emerson Fosdick preach realistically and effectively about the place that the Church can and should take in the community. Fosdick realizes that the creed is important only as a symbol of unity - and that the effectiveness of the Church must be judged by different standards from those of its theology.
This passage points to an interesting way of thinking about the usefulness of creeds in organizing for justice work. I guess justice work includes climate change, but why not just say climate change since that's the focus of this paper. Creeds here are things that can be reflected on and "preached" in ways that unify, but avoid becoming totalizing ideologies that disconnect from the factual world.

Ethics and Incentives

An important "creedal" issue for climate change activists is how to frame their message in a way that appeals to and motivates a broad array of audiences. As discussed above, the complexity of climate change requires the cooperation of people in many disciplines and in many countries over a long time period. In the United States, there has been a tendency to shy away from explicit discussion of justice issues with respect to climate change and to focus rather on near-term incentives of interest to Americans. For example, energy security, or clean energy jobs, or avoiding an influx of climate refugees.

I'm confused. Who are the creeds for? For the activists or to recruit more to the cause? I feel like most people significantly involved in movements like this already base their commitment around notions of "justice." Are there really environmental activists whose creeds are limited to the short term? I feel like you are equivocating the creeds of the movement with the rhetoric that surrounds environmental policy change. One is the organizing principle of the movement and the other is what the movement projects out in order to achieve its ends. Have I misunderstood?

This could usefully be clarified. The creeds are for both activists and new recruits. Part of my point is that people end up absorbing ideologies, even if they think they are only using them for short term political purposes. We become our political poses. Part of my argument is that a justice creed will help everyone keep their eye on the ball and will appeal to people as recruits as well.

Such an incentives-based creed is perhaps good politics in the short term, but assessed as a creed capable of undergirding a social movement seeking global change, it falls short. For the end of dealing effectively with climate change, it is a poor fit. Many countries will suffer much more from climate change than the United States, and in different ways, and the United States will become reluctant to pay to help them. Energy security is not a panacea because America is the Saudia Arabia of coal. Effective action will require sacrifice now for the benefits of people later, whose interests rarely factor into contemporary calculations.

>
>
There's room to expand, subtract, etc. as you think appropriate. Basically, I tried to spell out all the assumptions and reasons I thought were floating around in the background to make the message (or what I thought the message was) as clear as possible.
 
Changed:
<
<
It may seem a truism that good politics is not good policy. But one thing Arnold can teach us here is that since we are not all fully rational Thinking Persons, we are all prey to the allure of creeds. They are comforting because they simplify a complex and anxious modernity, and for that reason they are seductive. We do not always rationally select our political tactics to serve our policy goals. Creeds sometimes choose people, not the reverse. Once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of persistent facts.

However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what partial agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.

Why presume short-term incentives will run out? In the end, isn't this just political rhetoric crafted to drum up support for initiatives that we hope will have broader impact. Indeed, isn't that why these things always come down to factual contests between those opposed and those for? I don't see why we can't just keep inventing short-term goals until all the initiatives we want to pass have passed.

I think they will run out, and they arguably already have. When push comes to shove, there will need to be hard sacrifices and hard work done. A catch-phrase like energy independence is not going to be able to generate political support for the scale of work that has to be done.

According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement.

Right. Heroes are cut from a different mold and such movements build up around achieving larger goals. Is it any different with the movement we're discussing at present?

I'm not totally sure what this comment means.

An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

Devin,

As you know climate change is not a hot topic for me [no pun intended I'm sure], so I come to this with little knowledge of the shape of the movement. Against that backdrop, I raise the following three points:

1) I had trouble following your argument the first time around. Your transitions, both paragraph-to-paragraph and sentence-to-sentence, are choppy, so the argument meanders rather than flows naturally from one point to the next.

[Any specific suggestions on this front?]

2) Again, the lens of your analysis is squarely on the movement itself, but I really question if that's where it should be. I feel like the argument speaks more to the problem of coordinating policy change in countries where accepted policy rationales differ. In other words, isn't it just the rhetoric of policy reform that differs country to country rather than the motives of the movement as a whole? I thought the overall goal of the movement was "save the planet"--not "we're running out of coal/oil/whatever."

[My overall argument is that for the movement in the US to sustain itself and make progress on the issue, the justice frame is important - so it is about the planet, not about dwindling coal, or peak oil, etc. I don't really see justice and incentives as interchangeable rationales for identical policies. I think they're almost different worldviews that lead to different policies and differing levels of commitment to achieve those policies against fierce opposition.]

3) Also consider that the timeline on which capitalism approaches problems is necessarily shorter than that of other organizing principles. Because America and many other countries are capitalist, doesn’t that mean that the public will (and by extension, power) in those countries can only be swayed by arguments that discuss problems in terms of their short-term consequences? In that case, perhaps the only way of passing needed regulations at all is by coaching policy rationale in short-term incentives. If it’s this or nothing, won't changing it work against the larger goal? Ultimately, I find the argument unpersuasive because I assume that environmental initiatives won't be ratified AT ALL unless we appeal to short-term incentives. I guess I don't see why we'd be better off trying to get capitalism to recognize a kind of logic that doesn't speak to what capitalism wants.

>
>

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

 
Changed:
<
<
[The question of capitalism is a big one. It may be that this ordering principle is inherently antithetical to dealing with long-term externalities problems like climate change. However, I think it's not necessarily incompatible.
>
>
 
Changed:
<
<
The argument from political pragmatism does have appeal. The old saying is that half a loaf is better than no loaf. The problem I am raising with it here is that with this issue, the quarter of a loaf we can get from an incentives creed tailored for maximum political appeal will literally do nothing to solve the problem. It is as bad as no loaf, and worse, because it wastes energy (no pun intended) that could be spent on the kinds of things that might actually be helpful, though they are unlikely.]
>
>

Creeds and the challenge of coordination

 
Changed:
<
<
>
>
Thurman Arnold argues that creeds are “elements common to all social organizations, large and small, whatever their purpose.” 24. Creeds are ubiquitous because humans require them in order to sustain complex patterns of interaction over time. As he writes,” Society functions like an anthill. If we were compelled to plan each day how to get food into New York City and waste out of it, we would be lost and people would starve.” 26. For Arnold, then, successful organizations and movements necessarily have creeds that provide both a sense of cohesion to their members and a stage for coordinated action.
 
Changed:
<
<
Leakage is a hole in the strategy, but does it utterly cause you lose the war? Why can't we have the same policy objectives and just tailor the rationale to what will appeal to the largest political base country to country? Is there still a coordination problem that way? I feel like countries inevitably adopt environmental policy at different rates, so you can't get away from leakage--you're left just dealing with it the best you can. That becomes Phase 2, if you will.
>
>
With respect to dealing with climate change, however, this requirement is complicated by the fact that the movement must sustain coordinated action across many disciplines and in many countries. Because those most responsible for climate change will not likely suffer strict regulation unless they must, there is real danger of production simply migrating to other countries if just a few nations impose, for example, limits on carbon emissions. Should that happen, global emissions will remain unchanged and we will have failed to deal effectively with climate change. Special attention must therefore be paid to the implications of environmental activists organizing themselves around one set of principles versus another. Creeds that do not help sustain the international coordination needed to solve the global problem of climate change must be de-emphasized.
 
Added:
>
>

A creed of short-term incentives can’t support a movement to resolve a long-term problem

 
Changed:
<
<
>
>
This point becomes especially important as activists consider how to frame their message in a way that appeals to and motivates a broad array of audiences. In the United States, for example, there has been a tendency to shy away from appealing broadly to the people’s sense of justice. Instead, activists have chosen primarily to focus on incentives of immediate interest to Americans: energy security, clean energy jobs, avoiding an influx of climate refugees, etc. Such an incentives-based approach is perhaps good politics in the short term, but, assessed as a creed capable of undergirding a social movement necessarily seeking global change, it falls short.
 
Changed:
<
<
[Leakage will cause the loss of this war. There's not time for Phase 2. Also there's a prisoner's dilemma - no one wants to be the first to act because everyone's afraid of everyone else free riding and everyone knows that unless everyone acts soon there is no point to anyone acting.]
>
>

It takes our eye off the ball

The idea that good politics is not good policy may seem like a truism, but one thing Arnold can teach us here is that environmental activists risk compromising their ultimate goal—building a sustainable future—if they even pretend to ground the movement in short-term incentives. Movements expand based on the message they project, and as they grow, the character of the movement will naturally change to reflect the motivations of its recruits. Thus, even against the better judgment of its leadership, the movement to prevent climate change is liable to become its poses. And, once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of facts that obviously indicate a need for a different approach.
 
Changed:
<
<
>
>
It goes without saying that activists risk compromising themselves as well. We are not purely rational beings, and creeds are comforting and seductive; they simplify a complex and anxious modernity. Whatever their best intentions may be, activists are every bit as likely as the rest to absorb--and be transformed by--a creed of short-term incentives.
 
Changed:
<
<
Still, I think the strategy/coordination/creed issue has broad implications for other global initiatives. I look forward to see how you develop it further.
>
>

It makes international mobilization more difficult

In this case, by adopting such a creed, the spirit of the movement is channeled nationally inwards. This potential transformation is dangerous because it undermines the goal of international cooperation as a matter of course. Many countries will suffer from climate change in more and different ways than the United States. When the impetus for policy change is historically selfish, the United States may become reluctant to pay for problems it doesn’t see as its own. Thus, even if we are able to shortcut national policy changes, mounting substantive, international initiatives—i.e., the changes that can actually make a difference—will become more difficult. At this point, the situation is too dire to suffer additional problems of mobilization.
 
Changed:
<
<
[If you want to take a crack at rewrite, for clarity and structure (don't do any research, obviously), I'd be interested to see what you do.]
>
>

It saps time and energy we could be spending more productively

Moreover, short-term incentives can fuel the movement only so long. For example, energy security can be no panacea because America is the Saudi Arabia of coal. This leaves activists continuously inventing new, more pressing reasons for changes to existing environmental policy, which in turn makes the movement more vulnerable to attack by its opposition. Instead of pursuing effective climate policy, the game becomes, as we have seen, a contest about the factual circumstances behind one short-term incentive or another. Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least it provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.
 
Changed:
<
<
>
>

The goal should be environmental justice

 
Changed:
<
<
Shawn
>
>
In the end, effective action requires sacrificing now for the benefits of people later—people whose interests rarely factor into contemporary calculations. According to contemporary economists, however, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. Be that as it may, history offers examples of people who have selflessly dedicated themselves to pursuing justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King, Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These people who have struggled for justice rather than for their own gain can serve as examples for a climate movement organized around a justice-based creed.
 \ No newline at end of file

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 16 - 24 May 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

Line: 69 to 69
 1) I had trouble following your argument the first time around. Your transitions, both paragraph-to-paragraph and sentence-to-sentence, are choppy, so the argument meanders rather than flows naturally from one point to the next.
Changed:
<
<
[Please feel free to edit any spots that scream out to you on this front]
>
>

[Any specific suggestions on this front?]

 2) Again, the lens of your analysis is squarely on the movement itself, but I really question if that's where it should be. I feel like the argument speaks more to the problem of coordinating policy change in countries where accepted policy rationales differ. In other words, isn't it just the rhetoric of policy reform that differs country to country rather than the motives of the movement as a whole? I thought the overall goal of the movement was "save the planet"--not "we're running out of coal/oil/whatever."
Added:
>
>
 [My overall argument is that for the movement in the US to sustain itself and make progress on the issue, the justice frame is important - so it is about the planet, not about dwindling coal, or peak oil, etc. I don't really see justice and incentives as interchangeable rationales for identical policies. I think they're almost different worldviews that lead to different policies and differing levels of commitment to achieve those policies against fierce opposition.]
Added:
>
>
 3) Also consider that the timeline on which capitalism approaches problems is necessarily shorter than that of other organizing principles. Because America and many other countries are capitalist, doesn’t that mean that the public will (and by extension, power) in those countries can only be swayed by arguments that discuss problems in terms of their short-term consequences? In that case, perhaps the only way of passing needed regulations at all is by coaching policy rationale in short-term incentives. If it’s this or nothing, won't changing it work against the larger goal? Ultimately, I find the argument unpersuasive because I assume that environmental initiatives won't be ratified AT ALL unless we appeal to short-term incentives. I guess I don't see why we'd be better off trying to get capitalism to recognize a kind of logic that doesn't speak to what capitalism wants.
Added:
>
>
 [The question of capitalism is a big one. It may be that this ordering principle is inherently antithetical to dealing with long-term externalities problems like climate change. However, I think it's not necessarily incompatible.

The argument from political pragmatism does have appeal. The old saying is that half a loaf is better than no loaf. The problem I am raising with it here is that with this issue, the quarter of a loaf we can get from an incentives creed tailored for maximum political appeal will literally do nothing to solve the problem. It is as bad as no loaf, and worse, because it wastes energy (no pun intended) that could be spent on the kinds of things that might actually be helpful, though they are unlikely.]

Added:
>
>
 Leakage is a hole in the strategy, but does it utterly cause you lose the war? Why can't we have the same policy objectives and just tailor the rationale to what will appeal to the largest political base country to country? Is there still a coordination problem that way? I feel like countries inevitably adopt environmental policy at different rates, so you can't get away from leakage--you're left just dealing with it the best you can. That becomes Phase 2, if you will.
Added:
>
>
 [Leakage will cause the loss of this war. There's not time for Phase 2. Also there's a prisoner's dilemma - no one wants to be the first to act because everyone's afraid of everyone else free riding and everyone knows that unless everyone acts soon there is no point to anyone acting.]
Added:
>
>
 Still, I think the strategy/coordination/creed issue has broad implications for other global initiatives. I look forward to see how you develop it further.
Added:
>
>
 [If you want to take a crack at rewrite, for clarity and structure (don't do any research, obviously), I'd be interested to see what you do.]
Added:
>
>
 Shawn \ No newline at end of file

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 15 - 14 May 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 14 - 13 May 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

Line: 9 to 9
 Sentences 1 and 2 do not seem significantly different to me. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem." I don't understand how this reference furthers your argument.
Added:
>
>

Fair point! Feel free to omit sentence 2 or 1 as you like.

"super wicked problem" is a term of art referring to problems that are very difficult solve. It's just an expression, basically.

 Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needfulneeded/necessary? I understand needful is a word, but it seems odd to me. changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to support the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of internationally coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.

Arnold's Theory of Organizational Psychology

Line: 21 to 29
 You're deploying Arnold as a way to think about creeds in a movement. I don't think it's necessary to spend so much time characterizing his argumentation in a paper of this length. Why not just pull out what you think is useful and move on?
Added:
>
>
Part of my project here is to help correct what I think is an incorrect interpretation of Arnold. Arnold is often characterized as as someone with an overly deterministic view of how institutions think. I'm trying to complicate that view and to defend my more (I think) subtle take on his argument. But, if you think it's a distraction from the central argument, feel to excise.
 However, at one point, he discusses creeds in a light indicating a certain recognition of human capability for self-reflexivity and agency. He writes of Riverside Church's famous former pastor:
With the recognition of the fact that church creeds are not searches for universal truth, we can understand better the function of churches in society. Preachers like Harry Emerson Fosdick preach realistically and effectively about the place that the Church can and should take in the community. Fosdick realizes that the creed is important only as a symbol of unity - and that the effectiveness of the Church must be judged by different standards from those of its theology.
This passage points to an interesting way of thinking about the usefulness of creeds in organizing for justice work. I guess justice work includes climate change, but why not just say climate change since that's the focus of this paper. Creeds here are things that can be reflected on and "preached" in ways that unify, but avoid becoming totalizing ideologies that disconnect from the factual world.
Line: 32 to 42
 I'm confused. Who are the creeds for? For the activists or to recruit more to the cause? I feel like most people significantly involved in movements like this already base their commitment around notions of "justice." Are there really environmental activists whose creeds are limited to the short term? I feel like you are equivocating the creeds of the movement with the rhetoric that surrounds environmental policy change. One is the organizing principle of the movement and the other is what the movement projects out in order to achieve its ends. Have I misunderstood?
Added:
>
>
This could usefully be clarified. The creeds are for both activists and new recruits. Part of my point is that people end up absorbing ideologies, even if they think they are only using them for short term political purposes. We become our political poses. Part of my argument is that a justice creed will help everyone keep their eye on the ball and will appeal to people as recruits as well.
 Such an incentives-based creed is perhaps good politics in the short term, but assessed as a creed capable of undergirding a social movement seeking global change, it falls short. For the end of dealing effectively with climate change, it is a poor fit. Many countries will suffer much more from climate change than the United States, and in different ways, and the United States will become reluctant to pay to help them. Energy security is not a panacea because America is the Saudia Arabia of coal. Effective action will require sacrifice now for the benefits of people later, whose interests rarely factor into contemporary calculations.

It may seem a truism that good politics is not good policy. But one thing Arnold can teach us here is that since we are not all fully rational Thinking Persons, we are all prey to the allure of creeds. They are comforting because they simplify a complex and anxious modernity, and for that reason they are seductive. We do not always rationally select our political tactics to serve our policy goals. Creeds sometimes choose people, not the reverse. Once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of persistent facts.

Line: 40 to 52
 Why presume short-term incentives will run out? In the end, isn't this just political rhetoric crafted to drum up support for initiatives that we hope will have broader impact. Indeed, isn't that why these things always come down to factual contests between those opposed and those for? I don't see why we can't just keep inventing short-term goals until all the initiatives we want to pass have passed.
Added:
>
>
I think they will run out, and they arguably already have. When push comes to shove, there will need to be hard sacrifices and hard work done. A catch-phrase like energy independence is not going to be able to generate political support for the scale of work that has to be done.
 According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement.

Right. Heroes are cut from a different mold and such movements build up around achieving larger goals. Is it any different with the movement we're discussing at present?

Added:
>
>
I'm not totally sure what this comment means.
 An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

Devin,

Changed:
<
<
As you know climate change is not a hot topic for me, so I come to this with little knowledge of the shape of the movement. Against that backdrop, I raise the following three points:
>
>
As you know climate change is not a hot topic for me [no pun intended I'm sure], so I come to this with little knowledge of the shape of the movement. Against that backdrop, I raise the following three points:
 1) I had trouble following your argument the first time around. Your transitions, both paragraph-to-paragraph and sentence-to-sentence, are choppy, so the argument meanders rather than flows naturally from one point to the next.
Added:
>
>
[Please feel free to edit any spots that scream out to you on this front]
 2) Again, the lens of your analysis is squarely on the movement itself, but I really question if that's where it should be. I feel like the argument speaks more to the problem of coordinating policy change in countries where accepted policy rationales differ. In other words, isn't it just the rhetoric of policy reform that differs country to country rather than the motives of the movement as a whole? I thought the overall goal of the movement was "save the planet"--not "we're running out of coal/oil/whatever."
Added:
>
>
[My overall argument is that for the movement in the US to sustain itself and make progress on the issue, the justice frame is important - so it is about the planet, not about dwindling coal, or peak oil, etc. I don't really see justice and incentives as interchangeable rationales for identical policies. I think they're almost different worldviews that lead to different policies and differing levels of commitment to achieve those policies against fierce opposition.]
 3) Also consider that the timeline on which capitalism approaches problems is necessarily shorter than that of other organizing principles. Because America and many other countries are capitalist, doesn’t that mean that the public will (and by extension, power) in those countries can only be swayed by arguments that discuss problems in terms of their short-term consequences? In that case, perhaps the only way of passing needed regulations at all is by coaching policy rationale in short-term incentives. If it’s this or nothing, won't changing it work against the larger goal? Ultimately, I find the argument unpersuasive because I assume that environmental initiatives won't be ratified AT ALL unless we appeal to short-term incentives. I guess I don't see why we'd be better off trying to get capitalism to recognize a kind of logic that doesn't speak to what capitalism wants.
Added:
>
>
[The question of capitalism is a big one. It may be that this ordering principle is inherently antithetical to dealing with long-term externalities problems like climate change. However, I think it's not necessarily incompatible.

The argument from political pragmatism does have appeal. The old saying is that half a loaf is better than no loaf. The problem I am raising with it here is that with this issue, the quarter of a loaf we can get from an incentives creed tailored for maximum political appeal will literally do nothing to solve the problem. It is as bad as no loaf, and worse, because it wastes energy (no pun intended) that could be spent on the kinds of things that might actually be helpful, though they are unlikely.]

 Leakage is a hole in the strategy, but does it utterly cause you lose the war? Why can't we have the same policy objectives and just tailor the rationale to what will appeal to the largest political base country to country? Is there still a coordination problem that way? I feel like countries inevitably adopt environmental policy at different rates, so you can't get away from leakage--you're left just dealing with it the best you can. That becomes Phase 2, if you will.
Added:
>
>
[Leakage will cause the loss of this war. There's not time for Phase 2. Also there's a prisoner's dilemma - no one wants to be the first to act because everyone's afraid of everyone else free riding and everyone knows that unless everyone acts soon there is no point to anyone acting.]
 Still, I think the strategy/coordination/creed issue has broad implications for other global initiatives. I look forward to see how you develop it further.
Added:
>
>
[If you want to take a crack at rewrite, for clarity and structure (don't do any research, obviously), I'd be interested to see what you do.]
 Shawn \ No newline at end of file

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 13 - 21 Apr 2010 - Main.ShawnFetty
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

The Challenge of Coordination

Changed:
<
<
To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringer limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, if other countries do not cooperate, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem."
>
>
To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. (1)If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringerstringent? limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. (2)What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, if other countries do not cooperate, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. Sentences 1 and 2 do not seem significantly different to me. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem." I don't understand how this reference furthers your argument.
 
Changed:
<
<
Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needful changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to support the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of internationally coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.
>
>
Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needfulneeded/necessary? I understand needful is a word, but it seems odd to me. changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to support the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of internationally coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.
 

Arnold's Theory of Organizational Psychology

Changed:
<
<
Arnold argues that creeds are “elements common to all social organizations, large and small, whatever their purpose.” 24. The reason for the ubiquity of creeds is that humans require them in order to sustain complex patterns of interaction over time. As he writes, “Society functions like an anthill. If we were compelled to plan each day how to get food into New York City and waste out of it, we would be lost and people would starve.” 26.
>
>
Arnold argues that creeds are “elements common to all social organizations, large and small, whatever their purpose.” 24. The reason for the ubiquity of creeds is that humans require them in order to sustain complex patterns of interaction over time. "Creeds are ubiquitous because..." As he writes, “Society functions like an anthill. If we were compelled to plan each day how to get food into New York City and waste out of it, we would be lost and people would starve.” 26.
 Most of his discussion of creeds seems to have the character of an iconoclast loose in the temple. He compares "the Yale Law School" to a Laramie social club, and American political discourse to medieval theological debates about humors.

But Arnold also backs away from his "ant-hill" analogy at various points in the text. He invokes his identity as a lawyer, as opposed to social scientist, and claims he wishes to avoid "the vice of definition." Arnold seems more preoccupied with the ways in which the American creed of capitalism forecloses understanding of how American society actually works and less with the details of how creeds operate.

Added:
>
>
You're deploying Arnold as a way to think about creeds in a movement. I don't think it's necessary to spend so much time characterizing his argumentation in a paper of this length. Why not just pull out what you think is useful and move on?
 However, at one point, he discusses creeds in a light indicating a certain recognition of human capability for self-reflexivity and agency. He writes of Riverside Church's famous former pastor:
With the recognition of the fact that church creeds are not searches for universal truth, we can understand better the function of churches in society. Preachers like Harry Emerson Fosdick preach realistically and effectively about the place that the Church can and should take in the community. Fosdick realizes that the creed is important only as a symbol of unity - and that the effectiveness of the Church must be judged by different standards from those of its theology.
Changed:
<
<
This passage points to an interesting way of thinking about the usefulness of creeds in organizing for justice work. Creeds here are things that can be reflected on and "preached" in ways that unify, but avoid becoming totalizing ideologies that disconnect from the factual world.
>
>
This passage points to an interesting way of thinking about the usefulness of creeds in organizing for justice work. I guess justice work includes climate change, but why not just say climate change since that's the focus of this paper. Creeds here are things that can be reflected on and "preached" in ways that unify, but avoid becoming totalizing ideologies that disconnect from the factual world.
 

Ethics and Incentives

An important "creedal" issue for climate change activists is how to frame their message in a way that appeals to and motivates a broad array of audiences. As discussed above, the complexity of climate change requires the cooperation of people in many disciplines and in many countries over a long time period. In the United States, there has been a tendency to shy away from explicit discussion of justice issues with respect to climate change and to focus rather on near-term incentives of interest to Americans. For example, energy security, or clean energy jobs, or avoiding an influx of climate refugees.

Added:
>
>
I'm confused. Who are the creeds for? For the activists or to recruit more to the cause? I feel like most people significantly involved in movements like this already base their commitment around notions of "justice." Are there really environmental activists whose creeds are limited to the short term? I feel like you are equivocating the creeds of the movement with the rhetoric that surrounds environmental policy change. One is the organizing principle of the movement and the other is what the movement projects out in order to achieve its ends. Have I misunderstood?
 Such an incentives-based creed is perhaps good politics in the short term, but assessed as a creed capable of undergirding a social movement seeking global change, it falls short. For the end of dealing effectively with climate change, it is a poor fit. Many countries will suffer much more from climate change than the United States, and in different ways, and the United States will become reluctant to pay to help them. Energy security is not a panacea because America is the Saudia Arabia of coal. Effective action will require sacrifice now for the benefits of people later, whose interests rarely factor into contemporary calculations.

It may seem a truism that good politics is not good policy. But one thing Arnold can teach us here is that since we are not all fully rational Thinking Persons, we are all prey to the allure of creeds. They are comforting because they simplify a complex and anxious modernity, and for that reason they are seductive. We do not always rationally select our political tactics to serve our policy goals. Creeds sometimes choose people, not the reverse. Once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of persistent facts.

However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what partial agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.

Deleted:
<
<
According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.
 \ No newline at end of file
Added:
>
>
Why presume short-term incentives will run out? In the end, isn't this just political rhetoric crafted to drum up support for initiatives that we hope will have broader impact. Indeed, isn't that why these things always come down to factual contests between those opposed and those for? I don't see why we can't just keep inventing short-term goals until all the initiatives we want to pass have passed.

According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement.

Right. Heroes are cut from a different mold and such movements build up around achieving larger goals. Is it any different with the movement we're discussing at present?

An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

Devin,

As you know climate change is not a hot topic for me, so I come to this with little knowledge of the shape of the movement. Against that backdrop, I raise the following three points:

1) I had trouble following your argument the first time around. Your transitions, both paragraph-to-paragraph and sentence-to-sentence, are choppy, so the argument meanders rather than flows naturally from one point to the next.

2) Again, the lens of your analysis is squarely on the movement itself, but I really question if that's where it should be. I feel like the argument speaks more to the problem of coordinating policy change in countries where accepted policy rationales differ. In other words, isn't it just the rhetoric of policy reform that differs country to country rather than the motives of the movement as a whole? I thought the overall goal of the movement was "save the planet"--not "we're running out of coal/oil/whatever."

3) Also consider that the timeline on which capitalism approaches problems is necessarily shorter than that of other organizing principles. Because America and many other countries are capitalist, doesn’t that mean that the public will (and by extension, power) in those countries can only be swayed by arguments that discuss problems in terms of their short-term consequences? In that case, perhaps the only way of passing needed regulations at all is by coaching policy rationale in short-term incentives. If it’s this or nothing, won't changing it work against the larger goal? Ultimately, I find the argument unpersuasive because I assume that environmental initiatives won't be ratified AT ALL unless we appeal to short-term incentives. I guess I don't see why we'd be better off trying to get capitalism to recognize a kind of logic that doesn't speak to what capitalism wants.

Leakage is a hole in the strategy, but does it utterly cause you lose the war? Why can't we have the same policy objectives and just tailor the rationale to what will appeal to the largest political base country to country? Is there still a coordination problem that way? I feel like countries inevitably adopt environmental policy at different rates, so you can't get away from leakage--you're left just dealing with it the best you can. That becomes Phase 2, if you will.

Still, I think the strategy/coordination/creed issue has broad implications for other global initiatives. I look forward to see how you develop it further.

Shawn

 \ No newline at end of file

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 12 - 18 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

Line: 29 to 29
 It may seem a truism that good politics is not good policy. But one thing Arnold can teach us here is that since we are not all fully rational Thinking Persons, we are all prey to the allure of creeds. They are comforting because they simplify a complex and anxious modernity, and for that reason they are seductive. We do not always rationally select our political tactics to serve our policy goals. Creeds sometimes choose people, not the reverse. Once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of persistent facts.
Changed:
<
<
However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.
>
>
However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what partial agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.
 According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 11 - 17 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

Line: 18 to 18
 But Arnold also backs away from his "ant-hill" analogy at various points in the text. He invokes his identity as a lawyer, as opposed to social scientist, and claims he wishes to avoid "the vice of definition." Arnold seems more preoccupied with the ways in which the American creed of capitalism forecloses understanding of how American society actually works and less with the details of how creeds operate.

However, at one point, he discusses creeds in a light indicating a certain recognition of human capability for self-reflexivity and agency. He writes of Riverside Church's famous former pastor:

Changed:
<
<
With the recognition of the fact that church creeds are not searches for universal truth, we can understand better the function of churches in society. Preachers like Harry Emerson Fosdick preach realistically and effectively about the place that the Church can and should take in the community. Fosdick realizes that the creed is important only as a symbol of unity - and that the effectiveness of the Church must be judged by different standards from those of its theology.
>
>
With the recognition of the fact that church creeds are not searches for universal truth, we can understand better the function of churches in society. Preachers like Harry Emerson Fosdick preach realistically and effectively about the place that the Church can and should take in the community. Fosdick realizes that the creed is important only as a symbol of unity - and that the effectiveness of the Church must be judged by different standards from those of its theology.
 This passage points to an interesting way of thinking about the usefulness of creeds in organizing for justice work. Creeds here are things that can be reflected on and "preached" in ways that unify, but avoid becoming totalizing ideologies that disconnect from the factual world.

Ethics and Incentives

Line: 31 to 31
 However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.
Deleted:
<
<
According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.
 \ No newline at end of file
Added:
>
>
According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. Another interesting example is Richard Stallman, who has steadfastly resisted the replacement of the free software movement's justice creed with the incentives creed of open source. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 10 - 17 Apr 2010 - Main.NonaFarahnik
Line: 1 to 1
Added:
>
>
META TOPICPARENT name="SecondPaper"
 

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 9 - 17 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

The Challenge of Coordination

Changed:
<
<
To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringer limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem."
>
>
To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringer limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, if other countries do not cooperate, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem."
 
Changed:
<
<
Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needful changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to market the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.
>
>
Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needful changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to support the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of internationally coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.
 

Arnold's Theory of Organizational Psychology

Line: 28 to 28
 It may seem a truism that good politics is not good policy. But one thing Arnold can teach us here is that since we are not all fully rational Thinking Persons, we are all prey to the allure of creeds. They are comforting because they simplify a complex and anxious modernity, and for that reason they are seductive. We do not always rationally select our political tactics to serve our policy goals. Creeds sometimes choose people, not the reverse. Once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of persistent facts.
Changed:
<
<
However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out. According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility.
>
>
However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out.
 
Changed:
<
<
But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain that can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.
>
>
According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility. But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain, can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 8 - 17 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<

Free Software, Climate Change, and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

>
>

Climate Change and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

 

The Challenge of Coordination

Deleted:
<
<
Thurman Arnold writes that creeds shape the functioning of organizations. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needful changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to market the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help develop an organizational psychology capable of supporting the work that needs to be done should be de-emphasized.
 To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringer limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem."
Added:
>
>
Thurman Arnold writes that successful organizations have creeds that provide a sense of cohesion to members and coordinate their actions. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needful changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to market the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help sustain the type of coordinated work described above should be de-emphasized.
 

Arnold's Theory of Organizational Psychology

Added:
>
>
Arnold argues that creeds are “elements common to all social organizations, large and small, whatever their purpose.” 24. The reason for the ubiquity of creeds is that humans require them in order to sustain complex patterns of interaction over time. As he writes, “Society functions like an anthill. If we were compelled to plan each day how to get food into New York City and waste out of it, we would be lost and people would starve.” 26.

Most of his discussion of creeds seems to have the character of an iconoclast loose in the temple. He compares "the Yale Law School" to a Laramie social club, and American political discourse to medieval theological debates about humors.

But Arnold also backs away from his "ant-hill" analogy at various points in the text. He invokes his identity as a lawyer, as opposed to social scientist, and claims he wishes to avoid "the vice of definition." Arnold seems more preoccupied with the ways in which the American creed of capitalism forecloses understanding of how American society actually works and less with the details of how creeds operate.

However, at one point, he discusses creeds in a light indicating a certain recognition of human capability for self-reflexivity and agency. He writes of Riverside Church's famous former pastor:

With the recognition of the fact that church creeds are not searches for universal truth, we can understand better the function of churches in society. Preachers like Harry Emerson Fosdick preach realistically and effectively about the place that the Church can and should take in the community. Fosdick realizes that the creed is important only as a symbol of unity - and that the effectiveness of the Church must be judged by different standards from those of its theology.
This passage points to an interesting way of thinking about the usefulness of creeds in organizing for justice work. Creeds here are things that can be reflected on and "preached" in ways that unify, but avoid becoming totalizing ideologies that disconnect from the factual world.
 
Changed:
<
<

The Experience of the Free Software Movement

>
>

Ethics and Incentives

 
Changed:
<
<
In this respect, climate change activists can learn a great deal from the free software movement, which has been particularly thoughtful about the content of its creed and the seemingly subtle but important implications of words.
>
>
An important "creedal" issue for climate change activists is how to frame their message in a way that appeals to and motivates a broad array of audiences. As discussed above, the complexity of climate change requires the cooperation of people in many disciplines and in many countries over a long time period. In the United States, there has been a tendency to shy away from explicit discussion of justice issues with respect to climate change and to focus rather on near-term incentives of interest to Americans. For example, energy security, or clean energy jobs, or avoiding an influx of climate refugees.
 
Changed:
<
<
Richard Stallman recognized the disconnect. There was a lack of creeds-end fit. A creed of open source may help convince corporations to help produce some powerful free software, but in the long term it provides no creedal counter to the sale and use of software which restricts user freedoms.
>
>
Such an incentives-based creed is perhaps good politics in the short term, but assessed as a creed capable of undergirding a social movement seeking global change, it falls short. For the end of dealing effectively with climate change, it is a poor fit. Many countries will suffer much more from climate change than the United States, and in different ways, and the United States will become reluctant to pay to help them. Energy security is not a panacea because America is the Saudia Arabia of coal. Effective action will require sacrifice now for the benefits of people later, whose interests rarely factor into contemporary calculations.
 
Changed:
<
<

Climate Change: Ethics or Incentives?

>
>
It may seem a truism that good politics is not good policy. But one thing Arnold can teach us here is that since we are not all fully rational Thinking Persons, we are all prey to the allure of creeds. They are comforting because they simplify a complex and anxious modernity, and for that reason they are seductive. We do not always rationally select our political tactics to serve our policy goals. Creeds sometimes choose people, not the reverse. Once creeds gel into an organizational psychology, they become difficult to change, even in the face of persistent facts.
 
Changed:
<
<
Similarly, for the climate movement to rely on the language of incentives may seem appealing. Energy companies have begun to rebrand themselves. However, this creed of incentive doesn't provide the means to support the types of sacrifices needed to deal effectively with global climate change, which will fall with greatest fury on the poor.
>
>
However, like Fosdick, we can seek to leverage what agency we can muster to develop creeds that invoke, to borrow a phrase, "the better angels of our nature." Emphasizing an ethical frame that expresses its goal as seeking justice, rather than optimizing incentives, may not be good near-term politics but at least provides a means of motivating action when individual incentives run out. According to contemporary economists, people do not act in ways that do not maximize their utility.
 
Changed:
<
<
Al Gore, in attempting to shift to an ethical frame, rather than an incentive frame, invokes the analogy of World War II. However - nationalist frame. Reliance on carbon based fuels has been compared to slavery. Quakers. Student essay.
>
>
But history offer examples of people who have dedicated themselves to working for justice. In American history, John Brown and Martin Luther King Jr. come to mind. These types of examples, of humans struggling for justice rather than for their own gain that can serve as the basis of a justice-based creed to organize a climate movement. An incentives-based creed will not be to deal with the long, complex, and demanding task of supporting a global approach to climate change.

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 7 - 16 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 

Free Software, Climate Change, and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 6 - 16 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<

Free Software, Climate Change, and the Importance of Creeds-Ends Fit

>
>

Free Software, Climate Change, and the Importance of Creeds-End Fit

 
Added:
>
>

The Challenge of Coordination

 
Changed:
<
<
"The predominant moral issue of the 21st century, almost surely, will be climate change" - James Hansen http://www.huffingtonpost.com/dr-james-hansen/obamas-second-chance-on-c_b_525567.html
>
>
Thurman Arnold writes that creeds shape the functioning of organizations. An important challenge with respect to climate change is organizing people to press for needful changes to climate policies in a broad range of countries. In seeking to develop such a coordinated movement, attention to the organizational implications of the creeds used to market the movement is essential. Put another way, there needs to be an assessment of creeds-end fit, and creeds which do not help develop an organizational psychology capable of supporting the work that needs to be done should be de-emphasized.
 
Changed:
<
<
almost surely
>
>
To deal effectively with climate change, there must be a measure of policy coordination across countries. If the United States adopts a climate law which imposes carbon emissions limits, and production simply migrates to countries with less stringer limits, global emissions will remain unchanged. This is referred to as the problem of leakage. What this means is that even if activists are successful in pushing for a strong climate law in their own country, they will fail to solve the global problem of climate change. For this reason, among others, Richard Lazarus has referred to climate change as a "super wicked problem."
 
Changed:
<
<
normative - should -
>
>

Arnold's Theory of Organizational Psychology

 
Deleted:
<
<
normative take on normative change
 
Changed:
<
<
what needs to happen for that to happen, though?
>
>

The Experience of the Free Software Movement

 
Changed:
<
<
consilient analysis: morality and motivation: psych, social psych, biology
>
>
In this respect, climate change activists can learn a great deal from the free software movement, which has been particularly thoughtful about the content of its creed and the seemingly subtle but important implications of words.
 
Changed:
<
<
leff: the spanish prisoner: altercasting; attractiveness of an altruistic role.
>
>
Richard Stallman recognized the disconnect. There was a lack of creeds-end fit. A creed of open source may help convince corporations to help produce some powerful free software, but in the long term it provides no creedal counter to the sale and use of software which restricts user freedoms.
 
Changed:
<
<
moral vision: john brown, quaker anti-slavery movement
>
>

Climate Change: Ethics or Incentives?

 
Changed:
<
<
compare: free software v. open source
>
>
Similarly, for the climate movement to rely on the language of incentives may seem appealing. Energy companies have begun to rebrand themselves. However, this creed of incentive doesn't provide the means to support the types of sacrifices needed to deal effectively with global climate change, which will fall with greatest fury on the poor.
 
Changed:
<
<
justice frame matters: have to be able to answer arguments about WHY to keep on struggling, when start to be pushback; claims that climate change hits poor mostly, so why should we care.

don'tr push the metaphor too tightly: acking the metaphor away from its metaphrand just a little more, so that the correspondences don't become so overtightened that the frame cracks.

arnold: different creeds: different organizational psychology implications

'm going to use the phrase "Free Software" to describe this material and I'm going to suggest to you that the choice of words is relevant. We are talking not merely about a form of production or a system of industrial relations, but also about the beginning of a social movement with specific political goals which will characterize not only the production of software in the twenty-first century, but the production and distribution of culture generally. My purpose this morning is to put that process in large enough context so that the significance of free software can be seen beyond the changes in the software industry alone.

This is a fascinating conversation, I've been thinking about it for fifteen years, I have a lot of fun doing it. I just want you to understand that such talk is the beginning of something way more important, and that in order to understand why it is important you have to understand why it is at all. It won't do to say it's Open Source--you'll get a good idea about the software business but you won't understand any of the rest of this because it won't be clear why what is happening is happening, or why the newspaper headlines read the way they do. What we are going through is a fundamental alteration in the areas of intellectual infrastructure and production all over the world. We're now talking about just one little piece. You have got to understand that the struggle is bigger than that. That it is more serious. That it commits us to fundamental moral questions that we have to take a side about. That the work we do as lawyers, and programmers and engineers now is about the future of freedom of ideas all over everywhere. That it means confrontations just as improbable in scale as the confrontation between the Microsoft Corporation and the Free Software Foundation, which I didn't name but which Mr. Mundie did. David and Goliath? Hell no. Goliath was just a big human being, basically the same as David but larger.

econodwarf - people only work for incentives > environmental economics/cost-benefit > veblen: workshmanship; autonomy.

distaste for futility: end with - why important to emphasize, this time, we win.

open source: incentive emphasized

free software: justice emphasized

McGowan? paper: holmes, gandhi

..... christianity and climate change article; other climate and ethics articles: framing as moral issue

john brown: moral vision; justice - thoreau commentary.

not fundamentally a technical issue, essentially; moral issue.

moral priorities and commitments - guide technical work, are embedded in technical work: free software concept.

>
>
Al Gore, in attempting to shift to an ethical frame, rather than an incentive frame, invokes the analogy of World War II. However - nationalist frame. Reliance on carbon based fuels has been compared to slavery. Quakers. Student essay.

DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 5 - 14 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<

The Importance of Creeds-Ends Fit

>
>

Free Software, Climate Change, and the Importance of Creeds-Ends Fit

 

"The predominant moral issue of the 21st century, almost surely, will be climate change" - James Hansen

Line: 32 to 32
 'm going to use the phrase "Free Software" to describe this material and I'm going to suggest to you that the choice of words is relevant. We are talking not merely about a form of production or a system of industrial relations, but also about the beginning of a social movement with specific political goals which will characterize not only the production of software in the twenty-first century, but the production and distribution of culture generally. My purpose this morning is to put that process in large enough context so that the significance of free software can be seen beyond the changes in the software industry alone.

This is a fascinating conversation, I've been thinking about it for fifteen years, I have a lot of fun doing it. I just want you to understand that such talk is the beginning of something way more important, and that in order to understand why it is important you have to understand why it is at all. It won't do to say it's Open Source--you'll get a good idea about the software business but you won't understand any of the rest of this because it won't be clear why what is happening is happening, or why the newspaper headlines read the way they do. What we are going through is a fundamental alteration in the areas of intellectual infrastructure and production all over the world. We're now talking about just one little piece. You have got to understand that the struggle is bigger than that. That it is more serious. That it commits us to fundamental moral questions that we have to take a side about. That the work we do as lawyers, and programmers and engineers now is about the future of freedom of ideas all over everywhere. That it means confrontations just as improbable in scale as the confrontation between the Microsoft Corporation and the Free Software Foundation, which I didn't name but which Mr. Mundie did. David and Goliath? Hell no. Goliath was just a big human being, basically the same as David but larger.

Added:
>
>
econodwarf - people only work for incentives > environmental economics/cost-benefit > veblen: workshmanship; autonomy.

distaste for futility: end with - why important to emphasize, this time, we win.

open source: incentive emphasized

free software: justice emphasized

McGowan? paper: holmes, gandhi

..... christianity and climate change article; other climate and ethics articles: framing as moral issue

john brown: moral vision; justice - thoreau commentary.

not fundamentally a technical issue, essentially; moral issue.

moral priorities and commitments - guide technical work, are embedded in technical work: free software concept.


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 4 - 14 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<

Creeds-Ends Fit and The Problem of Leakage

>
>

The Importance of Creeds-Ends Fit

 

"The predominant moral issue of the 21st century, almost surely, will be climate change" - James Hansen

Line: 18 to 18
 leff: the spanish prisoner: altercasting; attractiveness of an altruistic role.

moral vision: john brown, quaker anti-slavery movement

Added:
>
>
compare: free software v. open source

justice frame matters: have to be able to answer arguments about WHY to keep on struggling, when start to be pushback; claims that climate change hits poor mostly, so why should we care.

don'tr push the metaphor too tightly: acking the metaphor away from its metaphrand just a little more, so that the correspondences don't become so overtightened that the frame cracks.

arnold: different creeds: different organizational psychology implications

'm going to use the phrase "Free Software" to describe this material and I'm going to suggest to you that the choice of words is relevant. We are talking not merely about a form of production or a system of industrial relations, but also about the beginning of a social movement with specific political goals which will characterize not only the production of software in the twenty-first century, but the production and distribution of culture generally. My purpose this morning is to put that process in large enough context so that the significance of free software can be seen beyond the changes in the software industry alone.

This is a fascinating conversation, I've been thinking about it for fifteen years, I have a lot of fun doing it. I just want you to understand that such talk is the beginning of something way more important, and that in order to understand why it is important you have to understand why it is at all. It won't do to say it's Open Source--you'll get a good idea about the software business but you won't understand any of the rest of this because it won't be clear why what is happening is happening, or why the newspaper headlines read the way they do. What we are going through is a fundamental alteration in the areas of intellectual infrastructure and production all over the world. We're now talking about just one little piece. You have got to understand that the struggle is bigger than that. That it is more serious. That it commits us to fundamental moral questions that we have to take a side about. That the work we do as lawyers, and programmers and engineers now is about the future of freedom of ideas all over everywhere. That it means confrontations just as improbable in scale as the confrontation between the Microsoft Corporation and the Free Software Foundation, which I didn't name but which Mr. Mundie did. David and Goliath? Hell no. Goliath was just a big human being, basically the same as David but larger.


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 3 - 08 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
 

Creeds-Ends Fit and The Problem of Leakage

Line: 12 to 12
 normative take on normative change

what needs to happen for that to happen, though?

Added:
>
>
consilient analysis: morality and motivation: psych, social psych, biology

leff: the spanish prisoner: altercasting; attractiveness of an altruistic role.

moral vision: john brown, quaker anti-slavery movement


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 2 - 08 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
Changed:
<
<

Creeds-End Fit and The Problem of Leakage

>
>

Creeds-Ends Fit and The Problem of Leakage

"The predominant moral issue of the 21st century, almost surely, will be climate change" - James Hansen http://www.huffingtonpost.com/dr-james-hansen/obamas-second-chance-on-c_b_525567.html

almost surely

normative - should -

normative take on normative change

what needs to happen for that to happen, though?


DevinMcDougallSecondPaper 1 - 08 Apr 2010 - Main.DevinMcDougall
Line: 1 to 1
Added:
>
>

Creeds-End Fit and The Problem of Leakage


Revision 18r18 - 13 Jan 2012 - 23:34:21 - IanSullivan
Revision 17r17 - 03 Jun 2010 - 09:23:15 - ShawnFetty
Revision 16r16 - 24 May 2010 - 14:26:37 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 15r15 - 14 May 2010 - 00:52:07 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 14r14 - 13 May 2010 - 22:15:08 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 13r13 - 21 Apr 2010 - 23:59:31 - ShawnFetty
Revision 12r12 - 18 Apr 2010 - 16:35:45 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 11r11 - 17 Apr 2010 - 17:55:34 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 10r10 - 17 Apr 2010 - 14:35:55 - NonaFarahnik
Revision 9r9 - 17 Apr 2010 - 14:20:22 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 8r8 - 17 Apr 2010 - 02:02:59 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 7r7 - 16 Apr 2010 - 22:53:53 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 6r6 - 16 Apr 2010 - 20:39:54 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 5r5 - 14 Apr 2010 - 12:19:53 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 4r4 - 14 Apr 2010 - 01:22:56 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 3r3 - 08 Apr 2010 - 17:34:57 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 2r2 - 08 Apr 2010 - 13:33:08 - DevinMcDougall
Revision 1r1 - 08 Apr 2010 - 12:15:27 - DevinMcDougall
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM