Law in Contemporary Society

View   r5  >  r4  ...
EricSoehnleinFirstPaper 5 - 07 Aug 2009 - Main.EbenMoglen
Line: 1 to 1
 
META TOPICPARENT name="FirstPaper"
[ You didn't need to leave the original draft here, because all prior versions are saved. Look under the "Diffs" button. ]

Changed:
<
<
Fixing the Inside from the Outside: the Need for Creative Lawyering to do Justice to All By: Eric Soehnlein
>
>

Fixing the Inside from the Outside: the Need for Creative Lawyering to do Justice to All

  In examining the ways legal thinking develops and the way that thinking interacts with social constructs, we have failed to appreciate the problems of transitional equity that inevitably flow from changing the law. Just as Holmes cautioned that judges too often failed to “weigh considerations of social advantage” in the way they reasoned, we must be careful we don’t gloss over issues of transitional equity that arise when we try to change the world. Those changes will affect people who (whether they chose to buy into it or did so unconsciously) ordered their lives around activities the law had previously encouraged. Unfortunately, bright line rules in legal thinking or complete reliance on the protections of the political process don’t guarantee people are treated justly when we try to make the world a better place for all (and inevitably make it a better place for most). As lawyers we need to be astute as to who wins and who loses, and when those people are treated unfairly, we have to think creatively to use the law for just outcomes rather than mere just processes.

Line: 19 to 18
  So what’s the solution? While Kelo demonstrates that neither political nor judicial constraints always result in fairness to all, matters of social advantage are perpetually weighed by judges and political branches. At the same time, we should remember what Arnold informs us of -- men are born into society and espouse its principles, even if the principles have little to do with corresponding action. Thus, assuming ethical conduct, someone who conformed to those rules, while not necessarily purely “innocent” of misconduct at all times, certainly deserves some protection when the system they bought into goes up in smoke. This is consistent with Arthur Leff, who asserts that when men are forced to leave a relationship they need a degree of “cooling out”—a weaning off, or way of saying goodbye (what firms are doing to deferred first year associates?).

The aforementioned tenets of judicial reasoning and political process have been designed (after hundreds of years of thought by smart people) to work toward justice, but they can’t guarantee it in all cases. Although academia often encourages law students to think about problems in terms of “process solutions,” it is necessary we don’t lose sight of the small margin of people who get squeezed when we try to make things better. Although we’re fortunate enough to have to think about the academic exercise that is “the law,” as lawyers we have to be willing to work toward just outcomes, not mere perfect processes. As jobs 160k jobs vanish and Biglaw fails, I urge you to remember that it was fixing these inequities that brought you (or at least that brought me) here.

Added:
>
>
  • This draft is not an improvement, I think, but rather an amplification of the problems in the first draft. The first draft had three central problems with its argument: (1) the "innocence" of "losers" cannot be assumed in demanding Pareto-superior social policy; (2) the people who "play by the rules" are playing by rules that specifically say that the rules can be changed anytime; and (3) given (1) and (2), there's no moral entitlement in the established distribution of powers, rights and assets to oppose to the moral entitlement of those who have not enough. The present revision doesn't address any of those points successfully. Without any difficulty I could ind you a score of cases from half a thousand years ago stating flatly, as an uncontested proposition, that no one has a property right in a rule of law, meaning that no one has a vested interest in the rules. That's been the rule so long that only a law student could claim not to know it, and everyone who plays by the rules is aware that the rules can be changed. But you not only ignore this point, you build your whole draft around treating the rules as property, so you can complain about a Takings Clause case. Of course, to say that the "problem is well illustrated by _Kelo_" is true only if the problem you are talking about has a property right in it, which it doesn't.

  • And then, unfortunately, you misstate what's going on in Kelo. You lament that peoples' expectations of lifelong possession are defeated. But that's true in every exercise of eminent domain, and if we adopted that point of view, the takings clause would prohibit all takings, not require compensation. That's of course not the law. What's at stake in Kelo is whether the reason for the exercise of eminent domain, namely to increase development and enlarge the tax base, is sufficient justification to force the current holders to sell in return for full current market value. The issue is not whether New London can condemn the property for public use—everyone except you, Ayn Rand and the younger, less sensible version of Richard Epstein thinks that question was settled even before the Takings Clause was written. The issue presented in Kelo is whether "public use" includes forcing a sale at full market price to a private profit-making real estate developer to do something with the land that will enrich the public by paying more taxes. Oddly, you would find that no one believes the State is prohibited from forcing a sale to a private non-profit organization that will to a lesser extent enrich the public by paying fewer taxes. Columbia University, for example, can use eminent domain to acquire land on which to build in West Central Harlem, forcing sales at current market prices to the University (which stupidly paid current market prices when those prices were much higher than they are now), and no one would expect the Supreme Court to be at all concerned. So your analogy, which was a poor one in the first place because it ignored the central analytical issue you needed to face, wouldn't bear the weight intended because you got the case wrong.

  • Evidently, the right way forward is to leave this cul de sac behind, and to return to the central problem you were trying to deal with. The intuition that social change has a moral obligation of solicitude for the deserving rich is strong in you, as it is in some people. You do not find, as others do, something self-evidently appalling about advocating on behalf of those who find it easy to live comfortably from day to day doing nothing about the vast majority of humanity that has nothing. Well and good. Now you wish to bring that same sensibility to your study of law, and your particular effort at present is to explain why people should be more moderate in their efforts to change social life and the distribution of rights, powers, and assets because too serious an effort would result in "punishing" those who have a settled expectation of continuing benefits from existing rules. I've explained why the theory that the propertied have property in the rules is untenable—it's descriptively false and normatively trivial. You need to use a different argument to sustain the proposition.
 \ No newline at end of file

Revision 5r5 - 07 Aug 2009 - 17:31:34 - EbenMoglen
Revision 4r4 - 07 Aug 2009 - 15:55:48 - EbenMoglen
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM